LC 00488: verschil tussen versies

Geen bewerkingssamenvatting
Geen bewerkingssamenvatting
 
(18 tussenliggende versies door 2 gebruikers niet weergegeven)
Regel 1: Regel 1:
Laws of Form showed in a formal way that the observer and observed coincide. In particular, the mark of distinction (˥) established the relation between distinction and indication: there cannot be a distinction without indication, and the other way round. The distinction severs a space in a marked and a unmarked state. An observer can observe only the marked side of the distinction in the act of observing, the other side is his blind spot. So, everyone has blind spots, which you can put to the test by yourself by observing the Necker cube and the Rubin vase.
Second-order cybernetics (a.k.a. neo-cybernetics, or the cybernetics of cybernetics) recognizes the role of an observer in observed systems. The role of an observer cannot be ruled out in the way systems are perceived. Our actions in the present are guided by our experiences we gained in the past. In a sense, we can predict the future. We build a mental model of reality that shapes the way we look at objects, like things, other human beings and situations. That is, we behave according to our worldviews comprised of practices and experiences driven by assumptions and emotions. This is who we are. Our behavior is self-referential, i.e., our future thoughts and actions are guided by past experiences. We make our own decisions, although circumstances might limit our options, or even more extreme, we might be coerced in a particular behavior.


The cube can viewed from two perspectives, but not at the same time.
We are constantly sensing the world and adapt where deemed necessary. Adapting to changing circumstances in the environment but also the concepts and ideas put forward by other people. Maturana and Varela equated cognizing with living:
[[Bestand:Cube I.png|gecentreerd|miniatuur|'''Figure:''' viewing a cube from two perspectives.]]
If you have trouble seeing both perspectives, then the dotted, hidden edges might help to discern them.[[Bestand:Cube IIa.png|gecentreerd|miniatuur|'''Figure:''' first perspective to view the cube from.]]
[[Bestand:Cube IIb.png|gecentreerd|miniatuur|'''Figure:''' second perspective to view the cube from.]]
You see the vase or the two silhouettes, but again, not at the same time.


[[Bestand:Vase silhouettes.png|gecentreerd|miniatuur|'''Figure:''' do you see a vase or do you see the silhouettes?]]
cognizing = sensing the world → adaptation = living.
At any one time, one view is perceived, whereas the other view is currently in your blind spot. Not only in the moment you perceive you have a blind spot, the very way how you perceive have its (implicit) blind spots as well because of the distinctions you apply. You need someone else to point out your blind spots to you.


{{Include lesson learned|Lesson learned=LL 00022|Description=Stakeholders' worldviews may differ.|Reference=LC 000346}}
In order to adapt, there must be {{Cite|resource=Resource Bibliographic Reference 00088|name=a difference that makes a difference|dialog=process-bibliographicreference-dialog}}. That is, a difference according to our worldviews (self-referential) and the (implicit) decision (autonomy) to adapt in the sense of reshaping our worldviews (autopoiesis).
 
More formally, the process of cognizing and adaptation can be written in the formula:  O = WV(O). We view an object (O) according to our worldview (WV), which can be anything including a non-animated thing (for instance a chair) or a complex situation involving several stakeholders holding different opinions, and create a mental picture of the object (O). In the process of perceiving, our worldview is adapted repeatedly. In the end, we might reach a fixed point in which our mental picture corresponds with the object. Our worldview is a moving target and is continuously adapted in this process. Beware of the fact that the fixed point only applies for ourselves. It becomes a fixed point because in the end there is no difference anymore that makes a difference. No matter how someone looks at the object from different angles, the perceived object remains the same. It has become a static mental model of an object reflecting the real (dynamic) object somewhere out there in the world.
* O = WV(WV(O))
* O = WV(WV(WV(…)))
Thus, by continuously applying our worldview to perceive an object, a fixed point is reached eventually: O = WV(O). Von Foerster called these fixed points {{Cite|resource=Resource Bibliographic Reference 00087|name=eigenforms|dialog=process-bibliographicreference-dialog}} thereby acknowledging the groundwork of Spencer-Brown's Law of Forms. Again, although a fixed point can be reached, this does not mean that we have a complete perception of the object or even a correct one. It simply means that there is no difference anymore.
 
For interested readers, a bright and erudite account of observing systems can be found in {{Cite|resource=Resource Bibliographic Reference 00078|name=Processes and Boundaries of the Mind|dialog=process-bibliographicreference-dialog}}. Louis Kauffman presents an interesting {{Cite|resource=Bestand:Cybernetics of fixed points.pdf|name=cybernetics take on the fixed point equation O = WV(O)|dialog=process-file-dialog}}.


[[Bestand:First and second order observation.png|gecentreerd|miniatuur|403x403px|'''Figure:''' first and second order observation.]]
When you look at an object in the outside world, you are a first-order observer. A second-order observer observes how a first-order observer observes the outside world. So, the focus of attention is switched to ''how'' one looks, instead of ''what'' one sees. This is an important shift because it opens the possibility to thoroughly think through questions like: why is someone doing or saying things the way he does or says? The answers can be found in observing the distinctions that are made by taking a seconder-order point of view.
<accesscontrol>Access:We got to move</accesscontrol>
{{LC Book config}}
{{LC Book config}}
{{Light Context
{{Light Context
Regel 23: Regel 22:
|Sequence numbers=;
|Sequence numbers=;
|Context type=Situation
|Context type=Situation
|Heading=Blind Spots
|Heading=Observing systems
|Show referred by=Nee
|Show edit button=Ja
|Show edit button=Ja
|Show VE button=Ja
|Show VE button=Ja
|Show title=Ja
|Show title=Ja
|EMM access control=Access:We got to move,
}}
}}
{{LC Book additional
{{LC Book additional
|Preparatory reading=
|Preparatory reading=LC 00455
|Continue reading=
|Continue reading=LC 00489
}}
}}

Huidige versie van 11 nov 2022 om 23:51

Second-order cybernetics (a.k.a. neo-cybernetics, or the cybernetics of cybernetics) recognizes the role of an observer in observed systems. The role of an observer cannot be ruled out in the way systems are perceived. Our actions in the present are guided by our experiences we gained in the past. In a sense, we can predict the future. We build a mental model of reality that shapes the way we look at objects, like things, other human beings and situations. That is, we behave according to our worldviews comprised of practices and experiences driven by assumptions and emotions. This is who we are. Our behavior is self-referential, i.e., our future thoughts and actions are guided by past experiences. We make our own decisions, although circumstances might limit our options, or even more extreme, we might be coerced in a particular behavior.

We are constantly sensing the world and adapt where deemed necessary. Adapting to changing circumstances in the environment but also the concepts and ideas put forward by other people. Maturana and Varela equated cognizing with living:

cognizing = sensing the world → adaptation = living.

In order to adapt, there must be a difference that makes a difference (Gregory Bateson, 1 januari 1972). That is, a difference according to our worldviews (self-referential) and the (implicit) decision (autonomy) to adapt in the sense of reshaping our worldviews (autopoiesis).

More formally, the process of cognizing and adaptation can be written in the formula: O = WV(O). We view an object (O) according to our worldview (WV), which can be anything including a non-animated thing (for instance a chair) or a complex situation involving several stakeholders holding different opinions, and create a mental picture of the object (O). In the process of perceiving, our worldview is adapted repeatedly. In the end, we might reach a fixed point in which our mental picture corresponds with the object. Our worldview is a moving target and is continuously adapted in this process. Beware of the fact that the fixed point only applies for ourselves. It becomes a fixed point because in the end there is no difference anymore that makes a difference. No matter how someone looks at the object from different angles, the perceived object remains the same. It has become a static mental model of an object reflecting the real (dynamic) object somewhere out there in the world.

  • O = WV(WV(O))
  • O = WV(WV(WV(…)))

Thus, by continuously applying our worldview to perceive an object, a fixed point is reached eventually: O = WV(O). Von Foerster called these fixed points eigenforms (H. von Foerster, 1 januari 1981) thereby acknowledging the groundwork of Spencer-Brown's Law of Forms. Again, although a fixed point can be reached, this does not mean that we have a complete perception of the object or even a correct one. It simply means that there is no difference anymore.

For interested readers, a bright and erudite account of observing systems can be found in Processes and Boundaries of the Mind (Yair Neuman, 1 januari 2003). Louis Kauffman presents an interesting cybernetics take on the fixed point equation O = WV(O).























Referenties